Callahan on Block on Callahan
Not some kinky threesome: instead it is a preview of my forthcoming paper in Cosmos and Taxis, where I respond to Walter Block's critique of my paper, "Liberty Versus Libertarianism":
________________________
Professor Walter Block has done me the honor of penning
an extended critique of portions of my paper, “Liberty Versus Libertarianism.”
His response which addresses my comments on the work of the professor himself,
and on his mentor, Murray Rothbard. A vigorous attack being a much more
complimentary response to a paper than is a placid indifference, my thanks are
sincere. Nevertheless, I think Block has misunderstood the essence of my
thesis, particularly in his contention that I am only arguing “utilitarian”
points, and I contend that his reply would have been more cogent had he paid
more attention to the other parts of my paper. In writing this response, I hope
that I can motivate a mind as sharp as
Professor Block’s to actually engage with my entire argument, and not just
those portions of it that explicitly address his own work.
Block begins his response to my paper with a defense of
Rothbard’s idea that rights cannot conflict. He writes:
The former [Callahan] begins with a citation from the
latter [Rothbard] to the effect that “rights cannot conflict with one another.”
What is the basis for Callahan’s claim that rights can conflict with each
other? It consists of a quote from Aristotle to the effect that “the ‘admitted
goods’ of a society must be weighed one against another in sound, practical
political reasoning.” But “rights” are not at all the same thing as “goods.”
Surely, Rothbard would acquiesce in the notion that goods may conflict with one another in the sense that people must
choose between goods like ice cream and shoes…
Surprisingly, Block does not seem to have examined
this “quote” from Aristotle at any length, which would have led him to realize
the only quoted bit is “admitted goods.” Nor does he seem to have tried to find
out what Aristotle meant by this. If he had, he would have found that Aristotle,
invoking “goods,” was talking about the “maxims” that guide a society, or in modern
vocabulary, what “rights” citizens have, and not choices between ice cream and
shoes! (See McIntyre, p. xx [I MUST FIND THIS PAGE IN MY HARD COPY.])
Furthermore, the whole critique of Rothbard and Block in my
original paper is predicated on the critique of rationalism in politics that is
offered in the first and second parts of it. The particular complaints I have
about Rothbard and Block are abbreviated not because they are the sole basis of
my criticism, but because the reader is expected to have absorbed the earlier
parts of my paper. His neglect of all parts of my paper except those dealing
with his work and that of his mentor, Rothbard, is also on display when he
writes, “Rothbard is concerned with
justice; Callahan, with mere utilitarianism,” and again when has writes, “On
the one side are the utilitarians, of whom Callahan is broadly representative.”
He does not seem to have noticed that an entire section of my paper is, in
fact, a critique of utilitarianism (the section on Buchanan and Tullock), nor
that my paper is almost wholly “concerned with justice”: it contends that
Rothbard and Block are fundamentally mistaken
about what constitutes justice: they believe that justice requires shackling
all of society to some abstract scheme exalting one right (in their case, the
right to property) above all others, while I (following Aristotle) contend that
justice means balancing all of the “admitted goods” of society, carefully
weighing one rights claim against another.
Block goes on to
assert that: “Consequences are utilitarian considerations, very far removed
from issues of justice.” But this statement simply assumes that the
deontological vision of justice is correct, and that utilitarians’ focus on
outcomes has nothing just about it. But that is as wrong-headed as utilitarians
exclusive concern with outcomes. Deontology and utilitarianism are both
abstract conceptions of ethics, and therefore, partial and defective. Their
plausibility derives from two factors:
1) They each get
at part of the truth: it is true, as
deontologists insist, that principles are an important part of ethics. And it is true, as utilitarians contend, that
the consequences of one’s actions are an important part of ethics.
2) Each approach
is able to benefit from the defective nature of the other: so long as
rationalism is understood as the only possible approach to ethics, then, to the
rationalist, deontology appears to be the only alternative to utilitarianism,
and vice-versa. So deontologists can strengthen their appeal by pointing out
the obvious defects in utilitarianism (it ignores principles), while
utilitarians do the same by noting the obvious defects in deontology (it
ignores consequences). It is like a war between one’s right leg and left leg
over which is the essential limb in walking: each leg can correctly note its
importance to the activity, and also note the flaws in the argument of the
other limb that it is exclusively essential to perambulation. Read in light of
the critique of rationalism I offer in my original paper, Block’s invocation of
“Justice though the heavens fall,” is not a sign of purity, but of imprudence, which, in my (and the
commonsense) view of ethics, is a vice, and not a virtue.
Block goes on to claim that it is somehow illogical to argue that rights claims
can conflict with one another:
In logic, there are three main principles: the law of identity; the law of non-contradiction; and the law of excluded middle. The first means that a thing is itself; it is not something else. The second states that something cannot both be, and not be. The third establishes that either a proposition is true, or its negation is true; there is no other alternative. Rothbard’s view that “rights cannot conflict with one another” is merely an extension, from logic to ethics, of these three laws.
I’m not at all sure what to make of this passage. Does
Block think that, because logical truths cannot conflict with each other,
therefore nothing can conflict with anything else? Would he declare that the
statement: “Nazi Germany and Great Britain could not have been in conflict
during World War II” to be “merely an extension, from logic to international
relations,” of the laws of logic? Presumably not: to do so, he would have to
show that the concrete facts of international relations are just a sub-species
of statements in logic. It is pretty obvious that such an attempt must fail.
But despite his assertion that Rothbard has merely extended
the laws of logics into rights claims, Block makes no attempt to show that
rights claims are the same sort of entities as logical statements. Is “if A
then B implies that if A is true, then B is true as well,” a statement of the
same sort as “Jeb has an easement across Seamus’s land”? And I think there is a
good reason he doesn’t attempt to demonstrate this: rights statements are quite
obviously different than logical
truths. Rights statements are assertions of powers possessed by individuals which
may not be legitimately interfered with by other individuals. The claim that “I
have the right to control of that acre over there” is quite obviously different
than a proposition in logic, and is demonstrated to be true in an entirely
different way: we show the truth of our property rights claim by producing
deeds of sale and so forth, not by analyzing syllogistic logic. And such rights
claims quite clearly can and do conflict: the person clinging to the
balcony flagpole, in the scenario presented by Block that I cite in my original
paper, has a right to life, while the person whose balcony flagpole is being
clung to has a right to her property. Justice requires balancing these claims; whereas Block’s unjust solution to the conflict allows the balcony owner’s rights
claims to run roughshod over that of the person merely trying to save her own
life.
Block attempts to answer the charge that shooting the fall
victim if she attempts to climb off of the balcony flagpole is an absurd elevation
of the right to property over the right to life by noting:
Suppose that this woman with the gun was raped only the day
before by a man who resembles the flagpole holder. She is in not unreasonable fear of further
bodily injury, and even death. Who is Callahan to deprecate her subjective
assessment of the situation in which she now finds herself?
Why in the world does Block think I deprecate this
assessment? In our legal tradition, the fact that the person clinging to the
balcony looked just like the property owner’s recent rapist would undoubtedly
be taken into account in deciding whether or not the property owner is guilty
of murder. Block presents us with a false dichotomy: either we give the
property owner’s “subjective assessment” of the situation complete reign, or we
ignore her assessment entirely. But this is not at all what our current legal
system (as any reasonable legal system must, I contend) looks at here: instead,
we ask, “Was it reasonable for the
property owner to feel threatened by the person hanging onto her balcony?” If
it turns out she was wrong that this was her rapist, but the falling victim
did, indeed, closely resemble the rapist, she will probably get off or be
convicted of, perhaps, manslaughter. Block’s unexamined acceptance of the
“subjective assessment” of a person who is possibly a murderer would, in fact,
if applied consistently, destroy his own property rights regime: for instance,
if my “subjective assessment” of Block’s co-authoring two papers with me is
that thereby he was handing over all of his property to me, then per his own
principle, who is he to “deprecate” my “subjective assessment” on this matter?
But any reasonable court, including the anarcho-capitalist courts Block
advocates, would have to evaluate my “subjective assessment” for plausibility,
and would hopefully decide that it is absurd: whatever delusions I may
entertain, there is no reasonable basis for concluding that by co-authoring
with me, Block meant to grant me all of his property. Similarly, if the woman
owning the balcony had been raped by a large white man, while the person
clinging to her railing was a petite black woman, I would hope that even
anarcho-capitalist courts would decide that her fear that the clinger might be
her rapist was entirely unreasonable, and that she is guilty of murder, not
engaged in a “defense of her property rights.” And, contra Block, my case against
her is entirely based on the injustice
of her action, and not upon “utilitarianism”: whether or not one has been
recently a victim of a crime, it is fundamentally unjust to kill people simply on the basis of unfounded fears that
they might conceivably be a threat.
Similarly, Block mistakes my case against police torture of
suspects as turning on the utilitarian results of such torture; that is all wrong:
I contend that it is unjust for law
enforcement officials to torture suspects, even when it is absolutely clear to
those officials that the suspects are guilty. Every human being is worthy of
respect for their human person, and no one, whatever they have done, is ever justly tortured. The fact that
allowing such torture produces bad results is not the reason that torture is unjust; it is evidence that it is unjust.
Block writes: “Let
us suppose, however, that cops now have an increased
motive to create ‘evidence’ inculcating innocent suspects. Still, Callahan’s
criticism of Rothbard fails. For the latter is discussing justice, not utilitarianism.”
This is
nonsense: it is unjust for people to
be framed by corrupt cops, even if it happened to produce greater utility.
Block examination of utilitarian grounds for deciding such cases is a diversion: my concern is not about what maximizes some abstract concept of
“utility,” but about what actual
rules are most likely to produce just
outcomes. And Block’s dismissal of such concerns does not demonstrate his (or
Rothbard’s) greater commitment to justice: instead, it demonstrates their
obsession with achieving easy, deductive answers to conflicts, rather than
doing the hard work of actually trying to achieve real world justice by careful
balancing of competing rights claims.
Block also addresses
my horror at the Rothbardian idea that parents ought to be able to starve their
own children to death without consequence. He notes that, in response to the off-putting
nature of Rothbard’s original example, many other libertarians have sought to amend
Rothbard’s initial position:
Does the mother have any obligation, not to feed the baby,
but to notify others (church, orphanage, hospital, synagogue, etc.) that she is
no longer willing to do so? Of course she does, and this is not a violation of
the no-positive-obligations principle of libertarianism. Here, Callahan ignores
a rather large literature (Block, 2001A, 2003, 2004, 2008, Block and Whitehead,
2005) making precisely this case: that the obligation to notify is compatible
with the NAP.
Block’s argument here is simply that I addressed
Rothbard’s argument as he wrote it, rather than taking up the numerous attempts
to patch over how horrific the conclusion of that argument is, as Rothbard
initially framed it. I congratulate Block and others for recognizing the
problem and for their attempts to save Rothbard from the condemnation his
original argument rightly deserves, but it is hardly my responsibility to help
them in this venture, since I have shown that the argument rested on faulty
(rationalist) premises in the first place.
Oddly, despite
apparently lacking the time to read my entire paper, Block did have time to
make up objections to libertarianism himself. See, for instance, his whole
digression about Okinawa, Japan, and China. What this has to do with the many
arguments I actually made is unclear to me.
However, in his
eagerness to supply his own libertarian counter-examples that he can then
refute, Block actually undermines his whole case with his example of the niqab-wearing
witness. A Muslim woman’s right to free exercise of her religion suggests that
she should be able to wear such a garment wherever she is. But if she is in
court accusing another person of some crime or tort, the accused has a right to
“face” his accuser. Here is a clear-cut example of rights conflicting, offered
by Block himself! His “handling” of this obvious case of a rights conflicting is
to assert that anarcho-capitalist courts will resolve this conflict in various
ways, and that this result will be better than that achieved by statist courts.
Well, perhaps he is right about this: my paper was not intended to decide
between various judicial systems. But if Block is correct, it is because
anarcho-capitalist courts are better at
resolving rights conflicts than are statist courts! After all, if there
were no rights conflict here, and we could just deductively arrive at the
“correct” result, then all anarcho-capitalist courts should reach the exact
same, deductively correct, resolution to the issue. By admitting that just
courts might resolve this issue in different ways, Block has given away the
entire game.
In conclusion, I find Professor Block’s objections to my
paper to be based upon a very partial reading of my thesis, one focused
entirely upon my comments on the works of Rothbard and Block himself. He treats
these comments as if they were a standalone paper themselves, rather than
correctly understanding them as merely examples of the rationalism that is
evaluated in the first sections of the paper. In brief, while I am thrilled
that Professor Block chose to address my paper at all, I do not find his
objections to it, based as they are on a partial reading of it, convincing.
References
McIntyre, Kenneth B. The
Limits of Political Theory Oakeshott’s Philosophy of Civil Association.
Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 2004.
http://public.eblib.com/choice/publicfullrecord.aspx?p=879515.
I'm not sure why Block is worth engaging. Most, if not all, of his arguments can be seen for what they are (i.e., incredibly bad) by anyone who is 12 years old. He is another case of a libertarian trying to use economics to answer non-economics-related questions. Answers that usually involve some bizarre mish-mash of econ terminology.
ReplyDeleteYep, couldn't agree more. Block seems utterly insane. I just read his paper about why road blockades would never occur in a system of private roads. In it, Block attempts to debunk the "evil umbrella" arguement by claiming that property owners could simply just build extremely tall towers and add rotating extensions to them to homestead the airspace and prevent the malicous umberella builder from shrouding their properties in darkness. I just find the shear lengths that Block goes to in order to justify his libertarian theories of property and homsteading insane. Block himself even admits that his solution is bad but claims that modern cities are more than capable of living in darkness and implies that no serious harm would be done by the malicious umbrella builder. Even when confronted with a serious reducto that he admits tacit defeat to, Block still won't stoop down to pragmatism and admit that property rights are not absolute.
DeleteGene, in light of your posts on primary and secondary reality, I have to ask this: how do we get people out of their 'secondary reality'? From what I can gather, Block seems like a nice guy. And yet, some of the conclusions he reaches - via Murray Rothbard, who was not a very good philosopher (that is putting it mildly) - are absurd.
ReplyDeleteIf pointing out the absurdity of conclusions isn't enough, what else is there? Hmmm...
There's no point in trying to convince them. They have completely different intuitions to normal people. It's like trying to convince a slave owner before the civil war that owning slaves was immoral. They have simply too much at stake to change their position. Block has written 1000+ papers defending property absolutism and ancapism and is a senior scholar at the mises institute. He also has a massive cult following among ancaps that regularly donate to his blog and buy his books. So no, changing their minds is never going to happen. You might be able to change the minds of their followers but not there minds.
DeleteThis comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDelete"I contend that it is unjust for law enforcement officials to torture suspects, even when it is absolutely clear to those officials that the suspects are guilty. Every human being is worthy of respect for their human person, and no one, whatever they have done, is ever justly tortured. The fact that allowing such torture produces bad results is not the reason that torture is unjust; it is evidence that it is unjust."
ReplyDeleteWhat a boat load of nonsense. If you want to see why, ask yourself the following question: Why is it okay for the prosecution to rely on witness testimony if the prosecution has the ability to coerce or bribe the witness(s) into giving false information during their testimony. The answer is simple, any competent prosecutor needs to rely on more than just potentially baseless acusations to build their case against a suspect and would need to bring in additional evidence such as circumstantial evidence just to build a preponderance of evidence at the very least. If they failed to do so, the defense could easily shred their case by just casting doubt on the reliability of the witness testimony(ies) or bringing up counter evidence like an alibi.
If you bring the same logic/reasoning to torture, then it's clear that no prosecution could just convict innocent people just by citing "evidence" collected during a torture session. The defense could easily cast doubt on the "evidence" and have the prosecutions entire case thrown out by demanding the prosecution follow up on the "evidence" (ex: demanding the prosecution dig up the body of the murder victim or find the murder weapon based on the information they tortured out of the suspect). Thus, no prosecutors would be willing to torture a suspect unless they were absolutly sure that the suspect was guilty since they would have to prove the valiidity of the information they got out of the suspects or risk suffering punishments.
P.S-1: If you try to debunk my case by citing some kind of historical evidence, let point out in 99.99% of those cases, the suspects had no real ability to challange the prosecution. For example, the prisoners at Guantamono Bay had could not trust or depend on their lawyers because the DOD frequently used guards pretending as their lawyers to extract information from the prisoners during interrogations.
P.S.-2: If you try to counterargue that the prosecution could just torture or use the threat of it to pressure the defendant into accepting a plea bargin, let me point out that both Rothbard and Block by extension agree that any coerced confessions would be invalid so the prosecution can't just torture innocent suspects into admitting their guilt. Even if they the prosecution successfully did so, the defendants could just appeal their case to a higher Ancap court which would throw out the prosecutions case if they discovered that suspect had indeed been coerced into signing a confession or accepting a plea bargain.
Just a quick question, why does Rothbard and likely Block by extension think that it's permissible to torture a suspect when they also believe that the police do not have the power to even subpoena a suspect?
ReplyDelete"Jones is invited to defend himself against the charges, although there can be no subpoena power, since any sort of force used against a man not yet convicted of a crime is itself an invasive and criminal act that could not be consonant with the free society we have been postulating. " (https://socialdemocracy21stcentury.blogspot.com/2013/06/rothbard-on-private-protection-agencies.html#comment-form)
Rothbard even claims that it is a criminal act to use any sort of force "against a man not yet convicted of a crime" so defense agencies wouldn't even be able to subpoena a suspect and in theory, even aprehend them if they constituted a flight risk. This seems like a giant glaring contradiction that you should've brought up in your paper.